nm0146: okay before we start er brief announcement which is this er advertising er Philosophy Society weekend away that's not quite right is it a philosophy weekend away day still not right never mind er right er you may or may not have know about this but every year we have a weekend away in Wantage er it's in the sort of er Oxfordshire countryside er and right there'll be three presentations by students and i think you're let off some essay if you do this er but we already have do we already have papers don't know but anyway there's three there's er three presentations er and a discussion of those on the the topic for this year is er personal identity er and then there's er a long walk along this very nice countryside and some modest drinking which gets a bit immodest towards late Friday evening er so that's all good fun er if anybody's interested er some leaflets up here namex's organizing it so further details can be got from her and i'll leave these with the handouts at the end of the lecture okay so any questions on that just yet er it's in June the twenty-second to the twenty-third any queries going okay okay last week let me just close the door okay last week er i laid out various attempts to defend Kant's claim that the only morally good motive is the motive of duty it's the positive claim er and also to defend the negative claim that no motive of inclination can have any moral worth and we saw that there were problems with all of those arguments although one came out better than the others just had an unfortunate er implication which Kant wouldn't want to accept i don't want to go carry on trying to justify Kant's claims rather what i want to do now is assume that some sort of a case has been made and deal with some objections that are raised against this conception of what it is to be a morally good person or what it is for an action to be a morally good action right there's a number of sort of worries that people have which can be found expressed in writers like Bernard Williams who i'll come onto later and er Michael Stocker who i'll also cover later er first of all a couple of preliminaries right a morally good action for Kant is one that's done solely from duty er now one question one might ask is if you're acting solely from duty if you're helping somebody just from a sense of duty and then whenever you ought to help them you only ever help them from a sense of duty does this mean that you don't really care about them a sort of worry here is that er the very notion of duty suggests or implies conversationally at least the idea that you don't really want to do it right if you do some action out of duty that kind of suggests that you don't want to do it right so you might feel yeah you might want to go and visit your elderly grandfather and do so quite happily then you think about the cases where you do it from duty from a sense of duty go and visit your elderly grandfather well those'd be the cases where you don't really want to do it but you know you think oh i really should this er up off you go and go and get the visit out of the way well does someone do-, does the con-, very concept of duty and acting from duty imply that people really don't want to do what it is they ought to do and hence don't care about you know the cons-, er the needs of others or other people in particular that's one wo-, worry one might have i don't know what do you think i mean given what you know about or what i said last week about what it is to act from duty do you think that if you do act from duty that suggests that you can't really want to do what you ought to do and hence you can't care about say the needs of the other person or the other person well what is it to act from duty anybody what are you what are you what is it to act from duty sf0147: is it when duty is the the solely is the only er motivation for it nm0146: er that that that's true but er is there another way of expressing the thought that your motive is duty you know that you're acting solely from duty which make you know well what i'm looking for is another way of expressing that sort of motivational structure which doesn't carry with it the sort of negative connotations that duty does duty n-, it sounds sort of burdensome yeah like a nuisance you talk about the sort of duties one has in a certain job and the sort of always the implication is that this is rather burdensome something that er you may take on but it only because it's part of your job or you know 'cause morality requires it so what we're looking for is some sort of construal of duty acting from duty which doesn't carry those negative connotations with it sf0148: er perhaps instinct nm0146: er sf0148: rather than them actually thinking about it nm0146: yeah well should yeah the notion of should i mean it s-, it captures the same sort of er feelers' er duty but already it's starting to lose some of its negative connotrations connotations doesn't sound quite so contractual you know duty sounds very contractual sounds like the sort of things that you know you're bound by some sort of contract to do they're your duties your duties as a lecturer or whatever sm0149: can we know that the that the word duty was used in the same way the same context as it is today than than when say Kant was writing nm0146: right er well i can't tell you the answer to that as a ju-, sort of general thesis er about sort of nineteenth s-, or eighteenth century Prussia but it is true that Kant didn't for Kant it didn't have this implication so it was a good one point to make but the notion of duty as Kant understood it didn't carry these negative connotations it didn't as we saw i mean i quoted something e-, er from Kant er it was either last lecture or the lecture before where he says that actually if you're unhappy in the performance of your duty that rather casts doubt on your virtue you know so acting from duty from him mean a virtuous person is one who acts from duty clearly if that's right then somebody who acts from duty er mean the concept of duty as it's being used there can't carry these negative connotations of disinclination or burdensomeness and it certainly didn't have that connotation for Kant right so if you can't shed those modern connotations those negative connotations then use some other concept right don't talk about acting from duty but talk about say doing the right thing just because it's right and rightness doesn't carry those strong negative connotations that duty does even though these concepts are close to being synonyms sm0150: did Kant was your best possible will nm0146: your best possible what sm0150: yes the best possible will i mean good will nm0146: well this is what it is to have a good will is to be disposed to act from duty sm0150: is that about duty what is duty under your eyes under in the circumstances you don't know what your best possible will is nm0146: er i don't i don't think you have to have thoughts about your will when you act from duty you've got to have thoughts about what you should do sm0150: so d-, i thought Kant said it was good will nm0146: no it's the other way round a good will is one that acts from duty acting from duty is not acting with explicit thoughts about what a good per-, willed person would do sm0150: yes nm0146: er you know it's just to do the right thing because it's the right thing to do okay so that's one word of warning just a preliminary point er what makes it seem as though you can't really care about others when you act from duty is the idea that ac-, er duty carries with it that what you're doing is in some way burdensome yeah or a nuisance or the implication you don't really want to do it and if that were true if that implication were true er then whenever you help somebody from duty it couldn't be because you cared about them right 'cause the duty would carry with it that negative connotation which meant you didn't really but you've got to do it anyway right it doesn't have that negative connotation for Kant so don't let this the sort of the those modern connotations influence the way in which you understand this notion another worry some people have is a worry about spontaneity think somebody who always acts from duty will lack a certain spontaneity do you think you know every situation they come to they got to think mm right now what should i do here on the one hand i've got these considerations weighing in favour of this action mm not sure i want to do that and then all things considered well perhaps i should do that and eventually you get round to doing something right and if you're concerned about the morality of your action does this mean that your actions will lack a certain spontaneity 'cause you'll always be worrying about whether you're going to be doing the right thing or not mm well any thoughts got a fifty per cent chance of getting this right sm0150: some action which seem to attract more worth can be and spontaneous like the man who jumps on the hand grenade to save his comrades it's a spontaneous act nm0146: right but does it s-, been suppose he did that from a sense of duty t-, th-, would that prevent its being spon-, sm0150: well no i think it does i think he does it nm0146: i know but the point is not whether he does or not it's point is whether if he did whether that would stop him from spontaneously reacting in that way when he first of all got to think well you know is it really what i should do leap on i mean on the one hand i'm going to save those other people other pe-, i'm going to be scattered all over sm0150: nm0146: [laughter] is this really what morality requires of me perhaps i'll try and persuade him to jump on it you know and then get the same effect but i end up in one piece sm0150: but we can have s-, have spontaneous acts don't know whether that's another thing nm0146: yeah sure sure nobody's arguing that we don't have spontaneous acts the question is if you're motivating the way that Kant thinks is a good way to be motivated could your actions still be spontaneous sm0150: no nm0146: why not actually i was fibbing when i said you had a fifty-fifty chance as soon as you gave me an answer i was going to ask you why [laughter] yeah sm0151: yeah i think you c-, er can be so closely and act not directly from the motive of duty just this maxim is derived from therefore felt a general maxim to act in certain circumstances in a certain way you can act could act spontaneously like that nm0146: yeah i'm not sure that really i mean that all of that's right i'm not sure if it helps because in many situations more than one of your principles is going to be appli-, er going to be applicable er so you've still got er instead of weighing up particular considerations you're going to be weighing up which principles over wh-, override which other principles 'cause it you know might be that you can only help somebody by breaking a promise and you got a prin-, er er a principle of promise keeping and a pro-, a principle of benevolence well which one are you going to act you can't act wi-, in accordance with both of them so you then got to think well which one overrides the other so i'm not sure that that helps i mean one thing one might i mean i don't think he that someone who acts from duty does lack spontaneity or need lack spontaneity er the thought that they do is driven by the idea that in order to decide whether what you're doing is permissible you've got to make various complex judgements and typically that will take time er but if you think about other areas of our lives where we're constantly having to make very complex judgements er but have no problem acting spontaneously on the basis of those judgements er we can see that there's no conflict here and what i'm thinking of is you know driving a car right right when you're driving in a car you're making hundreds of judgements about how you should sort of respond you know and whether so and so's going to pull out on you whether some pedestrian might run out whether there's a dog up there not on the lead whether he's going to pull out whether the person's braking in front of you how hard you should brake you know traffic coming at you from all directions traffic lights signs all these things you've got to make judgements all various very complex judgements about er and you've got to re-, react very quickly right so it's a complex business any of you er who's learning to drive at the moment anybody here learning to drive guess you're already drivers anybody who's learning to drive know how horrible it is er so when you start out you got to think explicitly about these things and of course you can't react very quickly because you're you know you're having to think about everything you know in a very mechanical way but the point is that the better you are you become at this the more skilled you become at driving the more internalized these judgements are the more spontaneous they are you're still making those very complex judgements but it's kind of like second nature to you it only slows you down it only means that you can lack spontaneity when you're a sort of novice but the more skilled you are at driving the quicker you internalize those judgements er they're still going on they're still being made but when you see somebody's brake lights come on in front of you you've not got to think to yourself er ah you know is he braking or has he just turned his lights on ah hang on if he's both lights go on i've got to push this middle pedal down you know if you had all those thoughts you already hit him before you do anything er you just react straight away but all of those judgements are going on all those complex judgements are going on now i see no reason why it couldn't be just like that in the moral case when you're a moral novice right er right you got your moral L-plates on right and you're struggling away you think oh well this consideration pulls me that way and that consideration and er you know this this this this and er okay i think i should do that right when you're having mechanically to go through some process of moral deliberation in that way then sure as a moral novice you're going to your action's going to lack spontaneity just like the reactions of a learner driver are going to be very slow because of the complex judgements that have to be gone through in a very mechanical way we're just like the driver who eventually masters these skills can react spontaneously once they're mastered so in the moral case once you actually you know come good at making these sorts of judgements or at least think you are then you can make very there's nothing to stop you er responding very spontaneously even though your actions are informed by these very complex judgements er sm0152: er sometimes though er w-, it's easy to decide what you want to do when you're in a car 'cause if you're going to hit something you know you want to stop and you don't want to run into it whereas if you're making a moral decision it sometimes you might er you know it might be difficult to choose what you want to do nm0146: oh yeah sure i mean this is not to say i mean sometimes in a car ma-, how skilled you are you might not be sure what to do 'cause or it's an unusual situation er so you may not be sure what the best thing to do the what the way you'll react in a car is not just 'cause you don't want to kill yourself yeah if you wanted to then you ought not to drive in this i-, you might drive in some completely different way er yeah you just sort of th-, it's a s-, just the idea that i mean it do-, doesn't depend upon that the sort of judgements that are made are judgements about you know just what's going on around you and your own desires and preferences don't really come into it apart from you know your desire to get somewhere or other and of course in many moral situations where they're complex you really have to stop and think about it but then clearly you know it'd be inappropriate to try and make a snap judgement the real worry is is not that somebody who acts from duty is never spontaneous sorry the criticism is that they're never spontaneous not that they must always be spontaneous er but they'd lack a certain sort of immediacy in their responses and that would be a bit peculiar if we were like that er well once you think about what it is to master other skills and master other complex judgements in other areas you realize that it only slows you down when you're a novice once you get good at it you can make snap decisions and that there's no reason to think why that just couldn't be the case in morality actually morality is no more complex seems to me than driving a car sm0153: when you're driving a car you're try-, trained to make a reaction certain stimulations nm0146: well it's not just stimulus-reflex sm0153: nm0146: i mean there's all sorts of judgements going on sm0153: i mean child in the road you don't think do you because you've been trained child nm0146: yeah i know but if you're a novice you'll be thinking oh right er child right clutch down brake hard splat [laughter] sm0153: nm0146: dead child [laughter] yes [laughter] sm0153: nm0146: yeah but the thing is you're making snap judgements they're not just i-, it's not like tapping your knee and the foot sticks out it's just that you know you're not you don't go through those judgements you know and your reason doesn't go through some slow mechanical process er sm0153: but i told you the prior training was there nm0146: well that's right sm0153: yes nm0146: but there's no reason why moral training couldn't be just like that sm0153: of duty nm0146: well as i say there's no reason why moral training coul-, you know er if you're going to say that it there's something very different then you have to point out what the differences are why being trained to to drive a car works but being trained to be a sort of moral agent must always fail so you always got to have your L-plates on okay don't want to labour this point so i'm going to move on the rule cri-, so there's a couple of preliminary points a worry about er you know a sort of lack of concern for others and a lack of spontaneity i think they should they should be quickly put aside really 'cause they're not the main worries er with the notion of acting from duty the main worry that comes from this has been put forward by Michael Stocker and Bernard Williams i'll start with Michael Stocker and it's the the worry that the motive of duty's in some way alienating okay so this is what i'm going to focus on in the rest rest of the lecture er i'll just give you a quote er as to why Michael Stocker thinks that acting from duty might be er alienating what he thinks it might alienate you from is your friends and loved ones right so the worry here is that morality as Kant conceives it seems to stop you entering fully into relations of friendship and love I-E these valuable but non-moral relationships and he gives the example of a guy who's hospitalized and his well he somebody he thinks is his friend Smith they're always Smith er comes and visits him right so i'll just quote from Stocker here right you're very bored and restless and at loose ends when Smith comes in once again you're now convinced more than ever that he's a fine fellow and a real friend taking so much time to cheer you up travelling all the way across town and so on you're so effusive with your praise and thanks he protests he always tries to do what he thinks is his duty what he thinks will be best you at first thinks he think he's engaging in a polite form of self-deprecation relieving a moral burden but the more you two speak the more clear it becomes he was telling the literal truth but it's not essentially because of you that he came to see you not because you're friends but because it was his duty perhaps as a fellow Christian or Communist or whatever or simply because he knows of no one a-, more in need of cheering up and no one easier to cheer up unquote that's from Michael Stocker The Schizophrenia of model Modern Ethical Theories right so you imagine somebody who thinks doing something out of friendship and you discover that he's not actually doing it out of friendship he's just saying well look you know this is what i think i ought to do and i really strive to do what i ought to do er it just happens that visiting you in hospital is something i think morality requires and it's because of that that i'm coming to visit you not because you're my friend or because i'm worried about you right but because morality requires this of me right now if you i mean if Kant's account of moral worth meant that you got to be like this person like Smith then it does seem as though you're not going to be able to at least fully engage with non-moral relations of friendship and love loving relations 'cause morality you know you'll be always be doing things for the wrong reasons you'll be doing it because morality requires you to not because you know this person's your mate and he's bored er sm0154: er i don't know just surely in er maybe he's deciding that morality i don't know your it's your duty to go see this person you still have to choose which person you're going to see and you choose that person because he's your friend nm0146: er sm0154: as as opposed to nm0146: yes sm0154: the person lying next to him that you don't know nm0146: yeah yes but suppose er you did it not because he's your friend but because you feel you ought ought you know morally r-, morality requires you to help someone and you might yeah it's much easier to you know to help your friends than it is some stranger who doesn't know you you know going to cheer him up much more you know er than if i impose myself myself on some stranger okay who may not like me er er yeah some of the example-, i mean part of the quote says that er you know he chooses to go and visit you know his friend not 'cause he's his friend but because he's a fellow Christian or a fellow Communist or something like that not because he's in er his friend but it may be because he's his friend he knows that he needs cheering up and he's very easy to cheer up so you go for something you're pretty sure is going to work but that seems to be the wrong sort of reason to go and visit your friend in hospital right so i'm just sort of but i think you're right that there's something fishy about this and it stems partly from the first point i raised at the beginning of the lecture that it's making it look as if you're concerned with the morality of your action that will sort of take over and push out all other concerns but that's just the worry that Stocker's has thinks it's sort of er has this sort of dominating influence that once morality as Kant conceives of it gets in on the picture all other values are going to be pushed out right now the the way to respond to this er and i here follow er Marcia Baron er on this i mean all of the reading for this is in the er the reading list for the the lecture on the course handout the way to deal with this is actually to locate what it is that's disturbing about this particular case and once you've located where it is what you want to do is you know if the le-, if you find in locating what's disturbing about this it turns out that what's disturbing is his motivation Smith's motivation then you know that will cast doubt on Kant's picture of a morally good person but if it turns out to be somewhere else then it may not be that he's acting in this way 'cause he's a Kantian good-willed individual may just be because he's insensitive cold or something else but that's not Kant's fault right and the two things that Marcia Baron locates is wrong with him his A his b-, er his behaviour right the fact that he's so cold and uncaring he must realize that saying well i i'm not coming here to see you because i care about you i'm coming here just because i feel morally required to he must realize that's going to upset his friend [laughter] or if he doesn't then he's er he's suffering from some other vice namely complete and sort of er complete er insensitivity to others even even er people who seem to be his close friends what's wrong with what he do-, er with this situation is his actual behaviour his coldness his insensitivity his thoughtlessness okay but this is focusing on the way the things he says and his thoughtlessness and his insensitivity and none of those things are focusing on motivation i mean if i mean morali-, if his motivation is a concern for the morality of his actions it'd be very peculiar if he thought that morality required him to be cold insensitive indifferent er distant and all of these other things surely he doesn't think that so in acting in this co-, even if he does have no feelings for his friend at all it seems that morality would require him not to show that right you don't wear a great big placard saying i don't really care about you but you know i've got to come so here i am trying to cheer you up right so that the first thing that we locate is a-, what he actually does and says and certain vices that these his actions er express it doesn't seem to cast er for come to focus on the motive of duty the motive of duty's just doing the right thing because you think it's right but morality in no way requires him to be cold and indifferent in this very peculiar way another thing that's disturbing here is his lack of genuine concern for his friend there's well i'm not coming here because i care about you i'm coming here just because morality requires me to come here er and i know that you're a bit miserable and are pretty easy to cheer up so here i am trying to cheer you up there's nothing as i said at the beginning there's nothing about duty as such or the thought or a concern for the morality of one's action the means w-, that one must lack a genuine concern for other people or for one's friends or for one's loved ones mm now since the motive of duty doesn't make Smith act as he does in fact the motive of duty should make him act in quite a different way even if he doesn't care about his friend especially if he doesn't care about his friend and since it's not responsible that sort of motivation is not responsible for the apparent lack of concern he has for his friend it's not clear that the call although this is a very disturbing case it's one where you know you won't if that's what a friend is you don't want friends like that er the problem is not located in his motivation it's located elsewhere er does anybody want to come back on that yeah sm0155: what if his er morality er said that he couldn't lie and so he wouldn't be untruthful when his friend so thankful and like didn't want to claim praise where it wasn't due nm0146: yeah yeah well there's i mean there's going to be cases where what morality requires of you is going to conflict and one thing it requires you not to do is not to to to lie er but also tells you not to hurt people unnecessarily and so this is one of those conflict cases and it may be that er you know you think that the requirement not to lie outweighs the requirement not to upset people but even so and you sh-, that still doesn't mean that you should sort of tell the truth in this cold way sm0156: not totally i mean from the suggestion i got from the the example was that was so [laughter] overtly thanking him he was like saying thank you every se-, every couple of you know words nm0146: right sm0156: the other person would be like oh well you know he wouldn't have up to that point had he not be so over the top in his thanks nm0146: yeah yeah sm0156: it and say well it was my duty nm0146: yes well er that's one construal of it perhaps sort of gets the blame somewhere else er seems to me that er well you can imagine a similar situation where somebody's just all too willing to reveal their true feelings of indifference and coldness and so at every opportunity it will pop up even though they're not being you know praised for something er you they don't think they deserve praise for er so you can think of a sort of a a very close situation where no blame can be put on er his hospitalized friend er well you know praising him too much er where all the blame would land on this individiual and then all the same questions would pop up okay well er let's move on that's Michael Stocker's criticism if er move on to Bernard Williams' criticism and these are all very closely er aligned these are all really driving at the same sort of worry but from slightly different angles now Bernard Williams has two worries the first is that the motive of duty rules out other motives that if you act from duty you can't act from friendship or love right so the worry here is that other other motivations get pushed out and since those other motivations are constitutive of what it is to enter into these valuable non-moral relationships if they're pushed off the scene by the motive of duty then it means then being moral will stop you fully engaging in non-moral but nonetheless valuable relationships that's the first worry the second is er that the moti-, that if you always act from duty then you'll be motivated by explicitly moral thoughts about what you should and shouldn't do about what's permissible w-, about what's not permissible in situations when that's quite inappropriate er and the example very famous example Bernard Williams gives is of a situation where you know your ship sunk you're on the lifeboat and you've got a choice between saving your wife and saving some stranger er and he has this example of a Kantian good-willed agent who's er motivated to save his wife not just because she's his wife but because she's his wife and because it's permissible to save your wife in preference to a stranger so you know the sort of motivation there is partly moral it's a a thought about the moral permissibility of his action and he says that you know some for example his wife may have thought that the thought that she is his wife would be sufficient to get him to save her er the moral thought seems to be as er Bernard Williams famously put it one thought too many it's not clear what's quite so disturbing there but er i'll deal with these points er in order now once again er Barbara Herman er well it's the first time i've menti-, Barbara Herman and Marcia Baron tried to deal with this and they tried to deal with this first objection by distinguishing between primary and secondary motives they say that duty can function both as a primary motive and as a secondary motive and that once you distinguish these and realize that a mo-, a Kantian morally good person doesn't always have to have duty as a primary motive then sometimes other primary motives can come in and that's perfectly okay other motives could be friendship or love or whatever what is the primary secondary motive distinction well a primary motive is what you and i ordinarily think of as somebody's motives it's to act from some primary motive is to act from a consideration that you would cite if somebody asked you why did you do that right and your answer might be quite simple mightn't you why did you pull that woman out of the water the answer might just be well because she's my wife and er that might be it right in that case your primary motive is just the thought that she's my wife or it might be more complicated might be what motivates you might be a thought she's my wife and the thought that it's permissible to save my wife in preference to a stranger in such situations right so primary motives are just the specific reason you'd cite in support of your action er in a specific er situation it's the reason why you did what you did the specific reason for doing that specific s-, action now secondary motives or are are more like regulative principles which needn't always function as primary motives though sometimes they might for duty to function as a secondary motive is just for y-, er certain counterfactuals to be true right for example for duty to function as a secondary motive er would just entail that if you thought your action was wrong you wouldn't do it right so your actions are regulated by a concern for the morality of your action and that may just imply er that if you thought that your action was wrong you wouldn't do it or alternatively a subjunctive conditional you'll er you'll only well it's the conditional statement that if you'll only do some act if you think it's permissible now if to have duty as a secondary motive just means that if you only just means that if you thought your action were wrong you wouldn't do it as long as you don't think it's wrong duty needn't not figure as a primary motive it need not figure amongst the reasons you would cite for doing a particular action you presumably you've got all sorts of regulative principles all sorts of secondary motives right you might have a s-, a sort of self-interested regulative motive er principle namely if some action's going to kill you you won't do it right but does that mean that thoughts about your own you know death are always going to figure in your motivations well no you know if he asked you well why did you come in here today you might say well to hear the lecture it wouldn't be to hear the lecture and because you were sure that you weren't going to die if you came in here right even though if you thought you were going to die if you came in here you wouldn't come i take it you're not that keen to learn Kant right learning Kant were fatal then you'd i take it be happy to be ignorant right so even if you've got these regulative second order not second order secondary motives it doesn't mean that they're always going to be f-, er figure in your in the thoughts that act as your primary motives it just means that your action is regulated in a certain way and that'd mean you'd have no implication that you have thoughts with a certain content about your own eventual death or you know in the Kantian case about duty okay so is that is you get a a sort of basic idea of the primary-secondary motive distinction one is a particular consideration for doing or reason you have for doing a particular action the other is more of a general principle regulating the sorts of actions you're going to do you might have a regula-, you know i'll do this as long as it's not self-destructive right that might be it but in doing some particular action one of the reasons you would cite for why you did it would not be 'cause you didn't think it was going to destroy you you wouldn't have thoughts about your own destruction for the most part unless you thought there was some very good reason for thinking something's going to be dangerous similarly if your secondary motive is duty that just means so long as you don't think the action is wrong sorry you just means that you wouldn't do some action if you thought it was morally wrong that needn't imply that every time you act you've got a th-, a moral thought as a primary motive it need not actually impinge on your moral deliberatio-, er in your deliberation about why you should do particular actions that o-, is that okay questions on that sm0153: probably draw that out from the meaning nm0146: er sm0153: nm0146: oh i don't see why well actually Kant doesn't talk about motives very much sm0153: no nm0146: he talks about inclinations incentives well actually inclination's just a particular sort of incentive talks about triebfedern er which gets translated as er incentives and he talks about maxims so he actually very seldom talks about motives he say-, a-, one place he distinguishes motives from er incentives but it's just one of these many places where Kant makes a distinction just forgets about it straight away er and what does most of the work in Kant actually is maxims principles of action and they're not primary motives although they'll be picking out the sorts of things which er would count as motives for you counts as reasons for you so i think mean you're right Kant doesn't actually make this distinction himself but it's a a distinction that fits very neatly into the Kantian framework of practical rationality but er no y-, there is nowhere where he makes this distinction er that's not a problem i mean there's two ways you can go you i mean as long as it fits neatly into the Kantian framework then this could be a way he er this would be a w-, er a legitimate way for Kant to respond the fact that he doesn't respond in this way or s say these things is not really the point with all of these figures historical figures we're really considering how defensible their position is and even if they don't have a response to a particular criticism 'cause it wasn't made at that time or they just didn't think of it the real issue's whether they could respond er so i don't mean i don't think you need get too worried about that this is a perfectly decent way for somebody who's sympathetic to Kant to respond to the Williams style objection okay well once we've got this distinction up and running it's easy to see how you can apply it to Williams' objection about how duty seems to push out other motives remember the first worry you had was that once duty gets on the scene it pu-, it all i mean you can't act from friendship or from love and hence can't fully engage in those non-moral relations well once you've got duty as a primary and secondary motive on er established then you can see that there's plenty of room for non-moral motives to get in at the primary level at primary as primary motives for a a Kantian good-willed agent right to do something from friendship from a a for a Kantian er good-willed individual would just be for friendship to be their primary motive er and although they're they'll have duty still as a secondary motive that just means that they'll do they'll act from the primary motive so long as it doesn't prompt them to do something they believe is wrong right so any sort of non- moral rela-, er motive can get in at the primary level and the agent may act just from that motive all it means i-, for duty to act as a secondary motive is for them to regulate the sorts of actions they'll do from those non-moral motives at the primary level er in a certain way namely they won't act from those motives if those motives point them towards doing something wrong okay so is it clear how that works have to mo-, get a bit of a move on 'cause i'm running out of time here okay let me move on quickly to the final point i wanted to make which is the second part of Williams' objection this is about whether a Kantian good-willed agent can would would have too many moral thoughts explicitly moral thoughts and exactly the same point could be made with the primary-secondary motive distinction i mean a Kantian good-willed agent doesn't have to have an explicit thought at the primary motivating level about duty er in saving his wife in preference to a stranger he doesn't his motive his first his primary motives don't have to be A well because she's my wife and B 'cause it's morally permissible to save my wife in preference to a stranger in situations like this at the primary level the motivating thought could be solely a thought about his wife and his concern for her nonetheless he's still a Kantian good-willed agent 'cause his action is regulated by duty at the second as a secondary motive what that means is he'll save his wife just 'cause she's his wife unless saving her would involve doing something he takes to be wrong okay that this is morally permissible to save my wife now you make think even that's too er restrictive or sort of inappropriate having duty at the the as a regulative principle it's still there's something inappropriate about that but at that point i think the Kantian just dig their heels in and say well er that there's nothing objectionable about duty as a secondary motive and to make that clear you know just consider somebody who d-, who is whose actions aren't regulated by duty as a secondary motive er they're just motivated at the primary level by a concern for their wife that means that no matter w-, whether this action is right or wrong or whether they think it's right or wrong they're going to save their wives so you know just imagine a situation in which the only way you can save your wife is by throwing two kids off the lifeboat so you think oh great out they go wife in right well in such a situation like that as er Barbara Herman clearly points out this seems like a case where the the the individual has one thought too few right rather than one thought too many it seems if saving a wife involves doing something like that then you should pause to think well you know is this really sh-, okay to do this right er right and but you know being willing to pause to think about whether you should do this action in situation where it looks as though the only way you can do what a motive of love or friendship prompts you to do is by doing something that looks like it's wrong i mean that sort of moral regulatively regulative function doesn't seem at all objectionable it doesn't stop you spontaneously reacting to the c-, er the needs of your loved one or the concerns of your friend doesn't mean you've got to in some way not care about them all it means is that you won't do anything for them no matter what it is right there'll be a limit to the s-, er to what frien-, you'll think that friendship will permit you or will allow you to do okay right i'll stop there handouts at the front anybody who wants the leaflets on the philosophy weekend they'll be here as well