nm0089: well good morning everybody er last year i volunteered or was volunteered to give this lecture because somebody was on leave that somebody's come back and apparently i'm still giving the lecture i don't know how that happened but here i am and what i'm going to talk about is Marxism er and Marxist historiography since Marx linking up with what namex said last week and i think one of the points that er is very important about Marx is that Marx's ideas and i i think namex mentioned this last week are a sort of unique fusion of two separate categories of thinking first of all there is a strongly philosophical element to Marx Marx's ideas developed er as philosophical ideas in the first place and it was once he'd kind of developed a er a philosophical view of the world based on Hegel and other er thinkers of early nineteenth century Germany he then er began to observe the realities of capitalist society around him and this led to the second layer of his thought the kind of empirical practical pragmatic understanding of the society in which he lived now any aspect of Marxist thought has got these two things closely infused together and this makes it rather exceptional if you go back before Marx you had philosophers i mentioned Hegel Kant and others who were not social analysts and you had people who were social analysts Montesquieu er Adam Smith who were not in the true sense philosophers i'm not saying they didn't have ideas but they didn't have this fusion and many people have argued that er Marx came to his conclusions philosophically and then used the world around him to justify them and there's a very er the linkage between them i think is brought out by this perhaps the most famous quotation of from Marx from eighteen-forty-eight from his thesis on Feuerbach where he argues that philosophers have only interpreted the world the point is to change it so for Marx er understanding was simply a preliminary step to action and to changing things and it follows from this that for a Marxist history is as i've said at the bottom it's about analysing the present as well as the past with a view er to changing the future not necessarily foretelling the future but changing the future now it's with this background in mind that i want to talk particularly about two aspects really following from this the way that Marxist ideas developed and to jump in from time to time to talk about the way that development of Marxist philosophy began to affect the way they looked at history because that's our main concern here is the historiography of all this now the question which arose almost p-, er permanently in people's minds after Marx was the question of why was it that the revolution that he'd predicted had not come about and in many ways the philosophical responses and the other responses to Marx er in the late nineteenth century are answers to this question and stro-, and on into the twentieth century as well and the first stage in this process really was one which began with not Marx himself so much but Engels and the person who became the leading figure in Marxist philosophy after er after Marx Karl Kautsky the leader of the s-, German Social Democratic Party it's famous famously er quoted everywhere that Marx said in the latter part of his life as for me i am not a Marxist er and if that phrase meant anything it meant that the kind of processes which were going on with Marx's ideas towards the end of his life and certainly after his death in eighteen-eighty-one were ones which er w-, which er were not er in his view following up the main i-, the main er essence of his ideas in particular there were attempts to turn his ideas into systems into rules into laws they were becoming in the context of the time much more positivistic er and they turned into what some people have called vulgar Marxism er a very crude form of historical materialism and Kautsky very much er f-, pushes forward this er concept of vulgar Marxism and of scientific Marxism if we look at some of the major features of that sort er of vulgar Marxism or s-, or or or er this attempt to turn into a set of dogmas essentially the starting point for most versions of it was the economic er interpretation of history economics is the fundamental aspect of history everything arises er or can be explained in terms of economic conjunctures economic development er and and economic base er and that there is er in this interpretation i'll come on to that in a moment er er a model of base and superstructure but the economic interpretation argued the fundamental factor on which all other fac-, social factors depended was er economy particularly the means of production er and ownership of it the means of production in different societies being land in feudal society machines and industrial society capital and labour er capital in capitalist society labour in in a number of other societies as well and the way in which those means of production were organized and particularly who owned them hence the basis of class because classes were divided into those people who owned these means of production and those people who were employed to work these means of production er in Marx's terminology in in a capitalist society er the bourgeoisie and the proletariat so vulgar er Marxists argued very strongly for the economic er determination of society and this led er some and many of the tendencies continued in the twentieth century in fact in some ways Stalin is one of the er leading exponents of this particular version and crude Marxism as it was developed in the Soviet Union in the nineteen late twenties and thirties that society has a kind of basis and a superstructure the economy is the basis the superstructure is everything that's built on it social forms but not just social forms also ideas cultural phenomena er law er religion er what we're doing today er higher education whatever it happens to be all these things arise in this very crude interpretation from economic er economic er economic er origins and associated with this er is a stress on the on class interest and class struggle and the idea of historical laws and historical inevitability er in other words er the version of Marxism which is most often criticized by people who don't know much about Marx himself is often this particular version of Marxism this er version of Marxism which possibly Marx had in mind when he said he wasn't himself a Marxist but the first stage of development of Marxist ideas brings it into this rather er schematic positivist influenced er rule based idea of controlling history history working directly through laws and those laws being readily perceptible er and readily er understandable now er that interpretation doesn't satisfy everybody on a number of grounds and as i've said the key question in people's minds was why had there not been a revolution of the Marxist kind and the first bold effort to try to answer this question er was put was was one associated with er the name Eduard Bernstein in late er nineteenth er he developed these ideas in late nineteenth er early twentieth century er Britain actually although he was German h-, er er his British experiences meant a great deal to him and he began to argue that there were some fundamental flaws he didn't actually challenge the positivistic element so much he challenged the working out of some of those rules that we were looking at and he argued that in actual fact the the laws as they were understood by Kautsky and orthodox Marxists the laws of capitalist development were mistaken hence his ideas are often referred to as revisionism instead he argued that first of all the class idea that Marx had and i think that er that er namex emphasized last week let me just take that it's probably easier if i just take that completely off there er that all that classes will polarize the middle class will disappear the proletariat will sink into penury the peasantry will th-, will disappear the petit bourgeoisie will disappear under capitalism and everything will move out into a wide range of of of polarized classes according to Bernstein this was not happening and he argued that the middle class doesn't disappear in fact the middle class is the s-, is the class which is expanding most rapidly in Britain in the late n-, nineteenth and early twentieth century so far from polarizing and disappearing into a a class struggle between the impoverished and the super rich which is the crude interpretation of Marx er the development of capitalism was moving in a different direction and er the er lower classes were not disappearing and the reason for this was that ownership of capital ownership of the means of production was not as Marx thought polarizing through competition driving poor er er sec-, er er failed producers out of the market and creating a smaller and smaller number of big er successful producers er whether it be in agriculture or in industry so instead er Bernstein argued the middle class was getting broader the working class was actually getting richer its wages were improving it was owning more the petit bourgeoisie small land owners in particular market gardeners that kind of person were becoming more rather than less numerous and even shareholding was becoming dispersed through society so that from Bernstein's point of view er capitalism itself was beginning to evolve er a kind o-, would hopefully evolve into a kind of socialism which could be developed through pursuit of reformism through pursuing democracy through pursuing er the er current paths of capitalist development without revolution in other words he saw in an optimistic way that capitalism itself was dispersing ownership through society and once the ownership was dispersed through society was effectively almost a socialist society and that's i think behind that other rather mysterious quotation there the ultimate goal of socialism is nothing to me the movement is everything in other words for him the idea of future communism or whatever er i-, utopian society you had was not the crucial thing the crucial thing was the movement towards it er and the ideas that er the the the the the workers movement for reform for change bringing people together er things like trade unions eventually the Labour Party these were all things which were developing in a big way in the eighteen-nineties and around nineteen-hundred in the in Britain and he saw that as the way forward for the labour movement of course you'll realize that that is exactly the split which has occurred in the socialist movement in the twentieth century between those who follow the revolutionary path and those who follow this reformist path if you like Bernstein is the founder of New Labour maybe they don't even talk about socialism but the ultimate goal is nothing to me could certainly be said by er Tony Blair er but the movement is everything er and the idea that that er th-, i mean the the problem that arises from this that socialism is split of course has helped er to maintain socialism as a as as as a er an unsuccessful movement in most respects in the twentieth century in terms of er er in terms of what was expected in the late nineteenth century however not all Marxists were as pessimistic about the future although Bernstein i wouldn't say is pessimistic but they were they were less pessimistic than he was about the potential for er revolution and the revolutionary side of Marxism was given a new lease of life naturally by the Russian Revolution er but also by some ideas which preceded it and the er person er who engendered a number of these ideas is er Rudolf Hilferding a an Austrian economist and socialist er who himself ended up more of a Bernsteinian than a revolutionary but Hilferding as i've said like many others was interested in the question why hasn't there been a proletarian revolution and he argued that in fact what was happening under capitalism was a massive development of er what he called finance capital that capitalism itself was beginning to change there were i mean today we see a capitalism of giant corporations bestriding the globe larger than nation states holding nation states to ransom hence er the need or the drive to do things like put er er the European Union together to try to combat this by uniting nation states to try to control some of these big corporations er but he er argued that what had happened was that er capitalism had changed its nature in that in Marx's day the owners of capital were usually the direct investors of capital you invested your own money in what seemed to be profitable potential businesses by the end of the century according to Hilferding capitalism was now based not on individuals but on banks and other financial institutions which became gigantic pools lakes of anonymous capital er as they are today er you put your er you put your money into the bank or i suppose probably your overdraft in most cases but your money goes into the bank and er what happens to it where does it go the bank lends people money whose money is it lending nobody knows it's a great anonymous pool of capital which is not controlled by individuals you don't control where that money goes still less if you have pension funds or er er other er financial er services and so on and so forth and that money is is allocated by professionals who don't own the money er by professional financial advisers fina-, financial managers for these institutions investment managers and so on and so forth and he argued that this growth of monopoly capitalism was changing the nature of capitalism that it wasn't this was one of the reasons why there were super profits being made er and so on and so forth but this was taken up by some of the revolutionaries because he also argued perhaps here echoing a bit of Bernstein that capitalis-, this meant capitalism itself was becoming more organized this was a second concept he had organized capitalism for Marx capitalism was based on the anarchy of the market the in the inpr-, unpredictability of the market the market was a kind of er tempestuous ocean on which capitalist enterprises had to sink or swim er in order to protect themselves from this tempestuous sea capitalism is becoming more and more organized er finance capitalism is one way it's becoming more organized because this meant that there were links between big companies er and banks and heavy investors but also companies themselves were coming together into monopolies and cartels and and doing deals with each other to control the market the idea that capitalists like markets is laughable capitalists hate markets they like to control markets or don't like free markets they like to control markets and he was pointing to this as a way in which big capital had survived the predictions of Marx that it was changing its nature it was turning into what we think of as monopoly capitalism now the points from the revolutionary's poi-, er view is that certain revolutionaries Lenin in the forefront seized on Hilferding's ideas as a justification for the potential for revolution in the face of Bernstein's criticism er and Bernstein's revisionism because the conclusion which Lenin drew from Hilferding's ideas of organ-, organized capitalism was that here was capitalism itself developing institutions which could be taken over by a future revolutionary state because instead of having a whole inchoate class of capital owners running the capitalist economy you now had these key financial managers who were working for banks for salaries if you decapitated capitalism er and that in a se-, er in in Lenin's view meant nationalizing the banks you'd be able to control capitalist society this was the this was Lenin's assumption at the turn of the century from these ideas so by nationalizing the banks you could then control er you could then control er the evolution of capitalism control where investment went and you could control where er the priorities for society were and the fundamental problems of exploitation hopefully could be avoided by the state intervening and controlling this process and moving towards socialism so Lenin saw this as as a-, a-, as er monopoly capitalism as a step towards potential socialism because sen-, socialism is supposed to be a rational controlled organized society er one which was er in which human beings er called the tune and organized society the way they wanted it not one in which society called the tune and organized human beings in whatever was appropriate to the given economic er conditions of the day secondarily Lenin also looked at another phenomenon of the late nineteenth century as did Rosa Luxemburg and Nikolai Bukharin to argue that one of the reasons for the growth of these big monopolies and the expansion of capitalism was imperialism that er where Marx might have thought that capitalist ec-, capitalist er er r-, profit rates would fall because ca-, if capitalism was a kind of enclosed system once it became a global system the massive opportunities for what Lenin called super profits to be made by investing overseas and international trade and the monopoly companies were in the forefront of this and he argued that the most advanced workers of western Europe the wor-, the er er skilled workers of Germany and France and Britain were actually doing quite well out of capitalism as it was this is of course what Bernstein had also said because they were able to be paid by the super profits of imperialism so this was buying them off so to speak from their revolutionary potential er and Lenin also came to the conclusion that since imperialism is a global system you could have a revolution at any one point of it Bernstein er er Bukharin er was the first person to coin the phrase that capitalism could break at its weakest link er and Lenin's conception of capitalism was of of a global system with Russia as one of its weakest links so while Russia was not a capitalist society at the time of the Russian Revolution Lenin thought he was breaking the world system of capitalism by er attacking it at this at this weak link and from there it would spread to where it should take place in Germany er in France in Britain in western Europe and eventually who knows even in North America er s-, but Lenin er and these thinkers were still fairly much in the tradition of the semi-positivistic er interpretation of Marx since the Russian Revolution particularly since many people er on the left criticized the Russian Revolution and the way it was developing from very early on inclusing including Rosa Luxemburg who was very worried about the dictatorial and anti-democractic tendencies of Lenin and the Russian Revolution in nineteen-seventeen and nineteen-eighteen very early on er many er thinkers began to look in different directions for er new inspiration about Marxist ideas and these are ones which begin to feed in to er which begin to feed in to a new er way of looking at society er and these are ones which become particularly influential for twentieth century er Marxist hi-, and other historiography in particular a group of thinkers er began to move away from this er traditional as it were almost rule based er version of Marxism to drawing attention to quite different aspects of it to argue that the revolution had not occurred for amongst other things what we might think of in some way as cultural reasons that they turned our attention towards the issue of consciousness the political awareness of a given individual or a d-, given group of individuals er what role does this play in history we can't say that the economic base simply determines what everybody thinks what they think and the struggle for them to develop their own ideas and for them to er become er part of a larger movement focused around particular ideas and to become aware of their situation in society is one of the reas-, is one of the factors er why or or or the fact this hasn't happened is one of the reasons why society er why the revolution that Marx expected had not taken place and in do-, in in pursuing this area they began to open up a whole er whole range of issues er for social and historical exploration er in a sense the earliest of these although he's often forgotten is Antonio Labriola who was perhaps the first person to begin to break with er the more er positivistic interpretation of Marxism and he pointed to the fact that what materialist theory represented for him was the first attempt to create a sort of er general science general social science unifying different historical processes er the materialist theory is the culminating point of this process what he meant was that in looking at history and the way it develops er materialism and the materialist theory is the first to break away from the compartmentalization of history into religious history history of politics er history of the law constitutional history and so on and so forth and begin to look at human society as a whole and of course this has been er a massive er development in er twentieth century historical studies and twentieth century historical understanding that there is nothing these days which is separate from history and in particular er it's this er sort of holistic sense of history but Labriola's ideas er gave way to others which became er i think much more e-, effective in particular er i Georg Lukacs the Hungarian Marxist er and i've taken a couple of key er s-, er a couple of key er concepts from him er he developed the idea or this is present in Marx although er it's a technical point here that Marx's er philosophical ideas of the early er writings were not known er until the nineteen-thirties and the nineteen-forties because some of his key works had never been published until that time so in many ways Lukacs was er er er was was predicting er the er ideas of Marx which had not yet been er published and revealed and he emphasized the question o-, the issues of alienation and reification and i include reification particularly because many people have seen this as being crucially relevant to modern consumer society alienation is a concept which is present in Marx and er particularly in those early writings er s-, as i say only a few of which had actually been published at the time Lukacs was writing by which Marx argued that human beings could create things which they didn't recognize as their creations and kind of bowed down to them as though they were what controlled human beings in other words human beings had a had a a tendency to create their own masters in various ways and by looking at er a number of these things as social conventions rather than as ruling forces you could then take a step towards er overcoming this alienation and controlling them there were a number of important er er examples of this let's take er a very philosophical example a lo-, er Marx's view on this arose from some theological interpretations by Feuerbach whom i mentioned earlier about the idea of God Feuerbach argued that it wasn't God that created man it was man that created God because God was a human conception and a human construction so to speak and having created this er construction human beings then took it as a literal reality and began to obey er this er God which they themselves had created it seems a strange sort of theology i suppose to most of you but it has been quite influential amongst religious thinkers as well because it does point to the fact that knowledge of God as we or conceptions of God as we understand them are human creations there's no two ways about that er although that doesn't necessarily follow that God is a human creation in this sense but certainly the conceptions of God are and secondarily in more social terms er one could point to phenomena like er we have in foremost in our mind i suppose the market don't buck the market why not buck the market we made it it's our market it's supposed to be there to do what we want that is what er er Lukacs would argue these are human creations there's nothing s-, nothing sacred about the market the market is a human convention money is a human convention all these things are created by people so why do we bow down and worship them as though they were ruling over us er so many Marxists began to argue that the first step towards revolutionary action was to un-, with this level of understanding this level of combating of what appeared to be the fundamental rules of society around us and a special form of alienation was this one er which er w-, this one usually referred to as reification which is er defined roughly speaking er as transforming human properties into properties of man-made things er this of course has opened up a lot of discourse about the nature of modern consumer society and advertising and things like that when you buy a commodity these days it's often associated with things which are way beyond that particular commodity er you're buying fun you're buying happiness you're buying goodness knows what if you buy the right product if you can associate thirst with a can of Coca-cola you're winning aren't you er persuade people that they don't want a drink they want a Coke er you are moving towards er towards controlling or or or developing your own commercial interests over people and in a mass scale this idea that you can actually er er you you can actually influence people by er turning these human properties into commodities is o-, is referred to also as commodity fetishism i suppose we live in an age of commodity fetishism er as you're only too well aware i'm sure designer this designer that label this label that the right thing here the right thing there why are you buying those things er to be seen to be you to be to be with to to to to be buying the right things whatever it happens to be this is a form of reification it's not because you want them or y-, because you need them or because there's any particular er necessity to have a a pair of Calvin Klein underpants or whatever it happens to be er but you made but you still go out and people still go out and buy them er and er this is er what Lukacs would think of as reification now associated with that also moving into the cultural area is another one of those that group of thinkers er Antonio Gramsci er and Gramsci er developed a number of ideas but he's most well known for the concept of hegemony Gramsci spent most of his life in er or a large part of his life in Mussolini's prison system er and he had a great deal of time to reflect on these issues and perhaps not the greatest access to information but he argued that er the issue of consciousness was crucial because er the socie-, the crucial element in society or a crucial element in society which Marx had not really er allowed for in this particular way was the cultural domination of a particular class the ideas and beliefs which are shared by a wide proportion of a society the assumptions of that particular society the web of beliefs as it says here the institutional and social relations of a given society and through this through establishing a certain set of beliefs let's take the one one of those that i mentioned before if everybody believes in the market the people in whose interest the market operates of course er have succeeded in establishing that particular set of er concepts and beliefs in society and if people accept it that's fine for them maybe not quite so fine for the people who er do not er benefit so er thoroughly from the market and er this intellectual hegemony this cultural hegemony was the work of intellectuals now er for Gramsci everybody is in part an intellectual intellectuals are not entirely a separate class every form of labour has a certain intellectual content to it according to him er it's a question of the proportionality but he divided intellectuals into two classes organic intellectuals and traditional intellectuals roughly speaking i suppose in as far as he was concerned goodies and baddies traditional intellectuals those who established the hegemonic ideas of the time and organic intellectuals people who were associated with particular groups and classes in society and e-, and enunciated and and developed the ideas characteristic of those particular classes so different classes would have their own organic intellectuals er the working class would have its intellectuals the middle class would have its intellectuals the aristocracy would have their intellectuals intellectuals were part of every other class and int-, intellectualism was a part of almost every human being's er er part of every human being's er outlook on life although he obviously hadn't seen Do You Want to be a Millionaire [laughter] er er but the sphere in which this e-, evolves and which this battle takes place is another key concept which is talked about a great deal civil society because er one of the long term phenomena since the Middle Ages was the growth of er o-, of society and of important er changes and important forces in society outside the state and civil society was the area in which intellectuals battled out their different conceptions and in fact would conduct a kind of intellectual class struggle through the media the press television er and all the rest of it and and that er this was an area of political activity major political activity moving away from the kind of traditional Marxist emphasis on workers' movements trade unions er strikes and that kind of thing which were still important but for Gramsci the the additional element which was required was to move into a ch- , challenge the ruling hegemonic ideas of a given er period and a given generation now er what has all this got to do with er historiography a lot of these ideas had important implications and i think i've got er two or three er two or three er er concepts here i think we've got time to do this er what is how how is are these ideas beginning to affect how history is understood er first of all it i-, it's implicit that er according to a number of these ideas and i s-, er and i suppose both the consciousness ideas to some extent but even more the vulgar Marxist ideas the idea i mean most Marxists would argue that history was structural that the role of individual er men and women was not crucial in history er human beings would be the object of history not its subject the whole point of revolution was to change this relationship to turn them into the subjective history so they controlled their own history but er historical explanation moves away from the idea of great individuals and moves more towards the idea of groups of classes of structural problems er and so on and so forth secondarily i suppose er from the mid-nineteenth century we tend to talk these days about historical change rather than about historical progress er historical progress is something which er people are much more sceptical about today and we use the much more neutral word change to describe how the different conflicting forces we're talking about er impact on each other and create er a new situation it's also er and i've mentioned this already er has moved towards er history becoming more holistic so the history is not divided up into separate domains er it becomes er the object of the historian is to try to give much broader explanations touching on all aspects of of life er the the traditional fields in British historiography break up after the First World War er i've given a few examples down there and in the words of Gareth Stedman Jones before this happened no attempt was made to fuse this aggregate of specialist routines into a meaningful historical totality so er that is partly er the way in which er which historiography er began to evolve under the pressure of these kind of ideas which have come from other quarters as well but this was a major challenging area er going beyond that er i haven't talked in any great detail about the subject of dialectics because er it's a complex issue in itself but er having said that progress has given way to historical change er Marxist historians in particular tend to put stress on dialectical iss-, on on on diale-, the dialectical nature of historical struggles I-E that there are always conflicting forces that force A conflicts with B and very often this produces a synthesis of both those forces C which is different from either A or B and history moves co-, constantly dialectically because C then gives rise to its opposing idea D which produces E and h-, and this leads to an interpretation of history which is based on the constancy of change that there is no stability in history er nothing stays the same er that change is the normal condition of life rather than stability er we would probably not have a big problem er understanding that but conservatism with a small C is based on the opposite point of view that stability is normal and change is abnormal er and that er this er dialectical view of history shows that change is the fundamental bedrock of history er rather than er any form of stability or stasis secondly er the particularly the the Western Marxists raised as i've said the problem of consciousness er and added to the more positivist structuralist interpretations the whole issue of it being far too crude to simply say that complex er cultural phenomena like law and religion can simply be crudely related to the economic base of a given society these are much more complex and they need much more detailed examination they need to be looked at much more carefully and much more closely er you can't simply say Jane Austen is a f-, is a mouthpiece of the British upper classes that sort of thing although many er crude Marxist literary historians have attempted to do things like that er Lenin himself said that Tolstoy was just er largely a mouthpiece of the Russian landowning gentry which seems the most inadequate description of Tolstoy imaginable to anybody who's read him thirdly er these people drew attention to a whole new areas of historical subject matter obviously implicit in what i've been saying the development of capitalism itself er Marx analysed the capitalism of his day er the analysis of contemporary society and its evolution over the previous decades and centuries was absolutely crucial to this level of historical understanding er industrialization came into the picture er the er agitations of the oppressed classes er the ideas of peasants workers peasants and workers were almost entirely absent from historiography except as occasional intruders in peasant revolts or er er un-, er untidy uprisings of various kinds in the past there was very little interest in these groupings er and there was very little interest in in in er in revolutions it was thought rather crudely that it wasn't going to be possible to write the history of ordinary people because they didn't leave any traces behind but essentially this is the kind of argument which has been levelled at any er at many of the new phases of er historical interpretation it's not my job to bring this up to date but i can remember when gender history began to evolve er conservative historians again with a small C argued well there can't be any gender history we can't write the history of women because there can't be any evidence for it because if there had been we would have done it this idea that history is evidentially based and emerges er full blown out of the archives er in fact of course once people started asking questions about the history of women they went and found there was a whole new way of looking at e-, at at at at archives which already existed or material which already existed and whole swathes of material which had never been looked at the same had been done for peasants the same had been done for workers classes who had been er in the phrase hidden from history er it's a ques-, and and this points to the to the to to the er er this points to the er fact that historians no longer saw themselves as the subjects of historical enquiry er as or as outside it it led to the whole question of the role of the historian themself er i-, if in the nineteenth century traditional idea the historian was above history er and simply related what had happened er these ideas led to historians becoming part of the hi-, of the social process historians themselves are organic or traditional intellectuals they are part of the intellectual struggle they are part of hegemony if conservative or dominant ideas suggest that er women should not be emancipated historians over the past hadn't even noticed that they were unemancipated and then suddenly when the r-, issue of women's emancipation arises historians begin to turn towards it as a new question a new hish-, issue similarly in the nineteenth century national historians turn towards the history of their own nationalities historians in other words increasingly become part of the intellectual struggle er and see themselves as part of the intellectual struggle and in fact come to the conclusion that they cannot separate themselves from the society in which they exist this has led to er and again it's a territory that i don't want to jump into at this particular moment the sort of post-modernist extremes of this that er you go to so far that the histor-, that history at the end of the day doesn't tell you anything about the past because it's a construction of the historian er herself or himself er and er while most Marxist historians wouldn't go as far as that the the objectivity of history was undermined by this and the subjectivity of history was stressed that doesn't mean to s-, that doesn't mean to say one can necessarily conclude that one will need that that w-, one can go as far er as the post-modernists in saying that there's no such thing as history or we cannot know anything worth knowing about the past most historians would tend to disagree with that so if just to summarize at the end er if we look at er a number of points made by the Italian historian Momigliano quoted by Hobsbawm er arguing what had happened to history in the hundred years after Ranke er he stressed in particular two or three of the points that we've been looking at here a decline in political and religious history er national histories begin to look old- fashioned according to this er and instead of national and religious history history of the state er there's a major turn towards social and economic history er and the twentieth century has seen of course massive development in the late twentieth century massive development of social and economic history er it's no longer easy to use ideas as an explanation of history although ideas as i've been stressing have a role in history the concept that everything in history arises from ideas which had been prevalent er in certain schools of nineteenth century historiography er is much more difficult to sustain these days that ideas themselves are seen as socially i don't know whether to say conditioned or determined perhaps the best word is to say socially shaped er they don't arise full-blown unobjectively er in people's heads they are themselves partly constructed socially er and ideas themselves are related to the society in which they evolve er and although we can then er move on from that and say that one can look at explanations in term of social forces it still doesn't necessarily solve that thorny issue of the precise relationship between er the explanation of historical events and the explanation of individual actions what is the relationship between these two this is something which constantly puzzles historians and constantly puzzles philosophers of history can we go totally structural and say individual actions mean nothing probably not because at certain stages individual actions can weigh very heavily if Stalin had not been Stalin there may not have been a terror if Lenin had not been Lenin there might not have been a Russian revolution if Napoleon had not been Napoleon er the French Revolution might have turned out differently individual actions individuals may un-, certain under certain conditions be very effective but we can't go to the other extreme and say history is nothing but the accumulation of the action of individuals or dominated by the action of individuals because those individuals work in contradictory and sometimes complementary ways and it's what they do it's a resultant of what they all do together which in a sense changes history rather than what they do as individuals it's the resultant of of of of the collective actions of individuals very often which er which leads to social pri-, er issues so it hasn't actually solved this problem and finally as i've already mentioned it had become very much more difficult to speak of progress or of the meaningful development of events in a certain direction what is poshly known as a teleological view of history the idea that things are always moving towards some sort of goal er usually for the better er progress in the liberal historiography in the mid-nineteenth century future socialist society and perhaps communism in the Marxist interpretation of history er Marxism is seen as a kind of teleological history i-, itself is a kind of teleological history because it does see society rising through different stages towards er some sort of ideal er utopian er future er and this er vision er is is one which is shares er i-, well not the same vision but the er notion of that kind of progress is something which Marx shared with er many of his contemporaries who were liberals and one which is much more sceptically er looked upon today okay i want to stop there and er you should have a copy of a few items of bibliography which has been circulated er to add to what you've already got because these are quite interesting articles focused specifically on the issues i've been talking about Marxist interpretation of history and er Marxist interpretation of society okay